SPECIAL ARTICLE
Organ donation and family refusal. Bioethical reasons for a change
La donación de órganos y el veto familiar. Razones bioéticas para un cambio
Alejandra Zúñiga-Fajuri, José Molina-Cayuqueo
Centro de Investigaciones de Filosofía del Derecho y Derecho Penal (CIFDE), Universidad de Valparaíso (UV), Valparaíso, Chile (alejandra.zuniga@uv.cl)
Recibido en su forma original: 23 de agosto de 2018
Aceptación final: 3 de septiembre de 2018
ABSTRACT
Cases of next-of-kin veto, i.e., a family refusal to allow organs harvest contrary to donor wishes or when the law presumes consent, is a widespread practice that seriously harms thousands of people. This is a practice settled in many countries Family refusal to donate reduces an already shallow donor pool by approximately 43% in the Americas, 25% in Europe (37,3% in United Kingdom) and 54% in Asia.
Some countries, such Argentina, France, Colombia and Wales, current reversed its policy on organ donations to a system that prevents next of kin to dishonoring the donor’s wishes restricting the confirm donor status only with the National Donor Registry and unless evidence of their objection is produced. In part I we review the latest amended transplant legislation of those countries that are trying to change this scenario. In part II we question the most frequently cited arguments to uphold the next-of-kin veto right and the countries that successfully changed their legislation banning this practice to encourage organ donation. We conclude that it is imperative to change this practice because the harm caused by promoting the family veto is greater and more serious than the potential harm of not allowing it.
KEYWORDS: health care system reform; organ donation; health laws; bioethica; family refusal
RESUMEN
Los casos de veto familiar a la donación de órganos es una práctica generalizada que perjudica seriamente a miles de personas. Esta es una práctica establecida en muchos países. La negativa de la familia a donar reduce en un 43% las donaciones bajas de los donantes en las Américas, un 25% en Europa (37,3% en el Reino Unido) y un 54% en Asia.
Algunos países como Argentina, Francia, Colombia y Gales han intentado revertir su política de donación de órganos de modo de impedir que los parientes revoquen los deseos del donante. En la primera parte, revisamos las más recientes reformas legislativas de aquellos países que están tratando de cambiar este escenario. En la segunda parte cuestionamos los argumentos más citados para defender el derecho de veto de la familia. Concluimos que es imperativo cambiar esta práctica porque el daño causado por el veto familiar es mayor y más grave que el daño potencial de no permitirlo.
PALABRAS CLAVE: reformas legales; sistema de salud; donación de órganos; legislación en salud; bioética; veto familiar
INTRODUCTION
Cases of next-of-kin veto, i.e., a family refusal to allow organs harvest contrary to donor wishes or when the law presumes consent, is a widespread practice that seriously harms thousands of people. Family refusal to donate reduces an already shallow donor pool by approximately 43% in the Americas, 25% in Europe (37,3% in UK) and 54% in Asia.(15) Family members often experience substantial grief when losing a loved one and cannot bear the thought of organ harvesting. Their objections are often strong enough to keep health care staff from persevering; even when both the regulations and the law require honored the donor wishes.
Some countries, like Argentina, France, Colombia and Wales, current reversed its policy on organ donations to a system that prevents next of kin to dishonoring the donor’s wishes restricting the confirm donor status only with the National Donor Registry and unless evidence of their objection is produced.
We claim that next of kin chances of countermanding the wishes of the deceased should be minimized. In part I we review the latest amended transplant legislation of those countries that are trying to change this scenario. In part II we question the most frequently cited arguments to uphold the next-of-kin veto right and the countries that successfully changed their legislation banning this practice to encourage organ donation. We conclude that it is imperative to change this practice because the harm caused by promoting the family veto is greater and more serious than the potential harm of not allowing it.
1. PRESUMED CONSENT RESTRICTED BY FAMILY REFUSAL: LEGAL CONUNDRUMS
Although many people are prepared to donate their organs after death and apprise family and friends of their decision to do so, few see their wishes realized - not just because only about 1% of deaths occur under circumstances that make organ donation feasible, but because of next-of-kin objection.
In Brazil, according to data from the Brazilian Registry of Transplant, in 2017 the absence of family member authorization accounted for 43.8% of organs not donated.(21) This is a practice settled in many countries. The United States has an opt-in system or First Person Authorization (USA, UK or Australia)(7) that work much like a living will or advance directive. The United States Revised Uniform Anatomical Gift Act states that no one can override the deceased's previously expressed wishes regarding organ donation.(6) Although studies suggest that between 69 and 75% of adults would be willing to become organ donors, half of the families that are asked to consider donation after a relative has died do not give their consent to the procedure.(5)
Table 1. European Union countries
Table 2. Latin American countries
Table 3. Asian countries
Recent law reforms are trying to change this scenario. France has reversed its policy on organ donations to a presume consent system (2016-41). The new rules, which came into effect on January 1, 2017, must be followed even if it goes against the wishes of the family.(2)
In Colombia, the new Organ Donation Act (Law 1805/2016) provides for presumed consent. In order to prevent next of kin or health care personnel from dishonoring the donor’s wishes, the new law requires that, in cases of document concerns or inconsistencies, attending physicians confirm donor status with the National Donor Registry. This sole mandatory consultation under the law rules out a role for the next of kin.(3)
In Argentina, although the latest law specifies that donor wishes “will be honored regardless of manner of consent” the fact is that the next of kin are still called upon to testify to the donor’s preference.(1) In 2014, this resulted in a 48.6% family overrule rate.(10) The parliament recently approved (July 4, 2018) a presumed consent law reform called “Justina Law” that seeks to modify the legislation to avoid the participation of the family. Then, it will no longer be necessary to check the family to approve or revoke the deceased decision.
A similar situation occurred in Chile where, despite a recent reform that instituted a system of presumed, conditioned and absolute consent, donor wishes continue to be frustrated upon death by family refusal. In 2016 this led to a 51% drop in an already shallow donor pool.(11)
In 2015, Peru had 2.6 actual donors per million inhabitants and a striking family objection rate of 67.1%.(15) In order to improve this situation, Law 30.473, enacted in 2016, created an express, absolute consent system that can only be rescinded by the donor. The next of kin cannot contest donor wishes and health care personnel are not allowed to inquire about their views to this effect.
The United Kingdom had a donor rate of 20.3 per million inhabitants and a family refusal rate of 34.2%. In Walesthe 2013 Human Transplantation Act states that adults dying in Wales (with certain exceptions) are “deemed” to consent to donation unless evidence of their objection is produced.(13) “Wales uses a soft opt-out, meaning that it’s not intended to be legally enforced and that potential situations where doctors remove organs for transplant directly against the surviving family’s wishes will not occur”.(14)
Finally, there are countries that tried to change the family veto, not through legal reforms, but rather through important incentives. In Singapore despite doctors prefer to ask the families of the deceased for their consent and usually respect their wishes, the system does have a mechanism that provides an important “incentive” for families that authorize donation. Every time that an immediate family member permits an organ donation, he or she receives a 50% subsidy in medical expenses for the five years following the donation.(9) Israel, regulated by the 2008 Organ Transplant Act, has developed a system of express consent, wherein people can register their wishes by signing a donor card. In practice, although family refusal is allowed, there are important incentives for donation in place, as there exists a points system that gives preference to direct family members of those who have donated organs to be, in turn, organ transplant recipients.(8)
2. AUTONOMY OR FAMILY: TWO PARALLEL ORGAN ALLOCATION SCHEMES?
Current studies show that the principal reasons for families opposing donation are: denial and rejection of brain death,(21) social, cultural and religious beliefs,(22) the moment the request was made, little knowledge on organ donation (especially on the length of the procedure), feeling overwhelmed, preserving the deceased’s body,(23) unknown donor wishes about donation,(24) medical mistrust, fear about the organ trade, and fear of objection on the part of other family members or family division over the decision.(25) Finally, there are also family members that do not consent to donation due to the express rejection of this possibility by the deceased.(26)
The discussion about the legitimacy of family consent appears to be unsuitable in “presumed consent systems” because organs could be harvested from those who were not able to express their opposition due to reasons such as illiteracy, disorganization, apathy, or a lack of awareness or understanding of the system. In the case of Spain, some has argued that if it were not for the fact that families have the final say and judges play a subsidiary role, the system would be one of organ conscription very much resembling the practice of autopsy.(27)
Contrarily, “express consent systems” are coherent with the idea that organ donor registries are, indeed, a form of advanced directive, because they allow living persons to make decisions about their future after death. In this sense, allowing family refusal is inconsistent with the rights we generally think people have over their property and body after they die or lose mental capacity. And many would feel that their autonomy has been violated if their wishes about the disposal of their body after death were not followed.(28) In this opt-in system or “First Person Authorization” adopted in USA, UK or Australia, we believe that it is not ethical to even allow procurement health professionals to approach families to overrule the donor's decision.
Advocates of allowing the next of kin to override donor wishes argue that it is often the only means to reduce anguish among family members and lessen stress for medical personnel. They also argue that, in the case that the deceased has changed his or her mind about donation, harvesting should not proceed without next-of-kin confirmation. They further argue that overruling the next of kin could undermine confidence in the transplant system.(11) This consequentialist line of thinking deems it unwise to override the next of kin because they are likely to share their experience with others. If these experiences are disheartening, they could turn public opinion against organ donation.
On the contrary, we stand with the views of the European Platform on Ethical, Legal and Psychosocial Aspects of Organ Transplantation (ELPAT) Deceased Donation Working Group, which suggests that even after taking all of the above arguments into consideration, next of kin chances of countermanding the wishes of the deceased should still be minimized.(25) The harm caused by promoting the practice of family veto is greater and more serious than the potential harm of not allowing it. As such, and unless their objection is shown to stand on solid ground (i.e., the deceased had changed his or her preference about organ donation, or was unaware that the law provided for the presumption of consent), family members should not stand in the way of donation.
Indeed, family members have been known to subsequently regret a decision to prevent organ harvesting. This comes as no surprise, as these are often decisions made under very trying circumstances. In addition, many family members who allow organ donation to take place will, in time, find solace in the idea of having helped save a life or lives. A survey conducted in Brazil showed that over half of family members who had objected to organ donation would allow it if placed again in similar circumstances.
Finally, we also need to consider that family members should agree to organ harvesting in the same way people put up with other constraints put upon them by the authorities for good and valuable reasons, including protecting public health, criminal investigations, or disposition of bodies.(20)
CONCLUSIONS
It is true that organ donation requests are often mediated by decisions made by people who are facing intense upheaval: uncontrollable, unanticipated, unexpected and massive events whose impact can be incapacitating on a cognitive, emotional and motor level. This is also often accompanied by feelings of being unable to control the situation or respond effectively. But it is also true that it is unreasonable, highly inefficient and morally objectionable to allow family pain, however great, to result in deaths that could have been prevented.
Allowing legislation and health care practices to countenance next-of-kin veto in organ transplantation sends the entirely wrong message. Next of kin are led to believe that they hold actual subjective rights over the dead body and that they have the absolute right to decide on the matter, when, in reality, they should only have the right to receive information about the death and the removal of the deceased’s organs.
We argued that relatives do not have the right to override the donor’s stated. Their objections, while valid, clash with other strong consequentialist arguments in favor of proceeding with procurement. First, allowing family refusal is inconsistent with the rights we generally think people have over their property (and their wishes about the disposal of their body after death). Second, we can notably reduce the organ shortage and save the lives of waiting patients.
After taking all of the above arguments into consideration, next of kin chances of countermanding the wishes of the deceased should be minimized. In the opt-out systems, law reforms should prevent next of kin to dishonoring the donor’s wishes, restricting the confirm donor status only with the National Donor Registry. In the opt-in system or First Person Authorization (like advance directives) we must consider that, with certain serious exceptions, the decision of the donor needs to be unbreakable.
Conflicto de intereses: Los autores declaran no poseer ningún interés comercial o asociativo que presente un conflicto de intereses con el trabajo presentado y expresan su adhesión a la Declaration of Istanbul on Organ Trafficking and Transplant Tourism (2008).
Financiamiento: Fondecyt 1150013 (Fondo Nacional de Desarrollo Científico y Tecnológico, Chile).
BIBLIOGRAFÍA
1) Rivera López E. Donación de órganos y el papel de la familia. ¿Vale la pena repensar el tema? Perspect Bioét. 2016;20(37-38):46-53.
2) Francia. Loi 2016-41 du 26 janvier 2016 de modernisation de notre système de santé [Internet]. Disponible en: https://www.legifrance.gouv.fr/affichTexte.do?cidTexte=JORFTEXT000031912641&dateTexte=20181115 (citado 15-08-2018).
3) Colombia. Ley 1805/2016 [Internet]. Disponible en: http://es.presidencia.gov.co/normativa/normativa/LEY%201805%20DEL%2004%20DE%20AGOSTO%20DE%202016.pdf (citado 15-08-2018).
4) Rithalia A, McDaid C, Suekarran S, Norman G, Myers L, Sowden A. A systematic review of presumed consent systems for deceased organ donation. Health Technol Assess. 2009;13(26):1-95.
5) Cotter H. Increasing consent for organ donation: mandated choice, individual autonomy, and informed consent. Health Matrix Clevel. 2011;21(2):599-626.
6) Siminoff LA, Arnold RM, Caplan AL, Virnig BA, Seltzer DL. Public policy governing organ and tissue procurement in the United States. Results from the National Organ and Tissue Procurement Study. Ann Intern Med. 1995;123(1):10-7.
7) Isdale W, Savulescu J. Three proposals to increase Australia's organ supply. Monash Bioeth Rev. 2015;33(2-3):91-101.
8) Zúñiga-Fajuri A. Increasing organ donation by presumed consent and allocation priority: Chile. Bull World Health Organ. 2015;93(3):199-202.
9) Chin JJ, Kwok TH. After presumed consent: a review of organ donation in Singapore. Indian J Med Ethics. 2014;11(3):139-43.
10) Shepherd L, O'Carroll RE, Ferguson E. An international comparison of deceased and living organ donation/transplant rates in opt-in and opt-out systems: a panel study. BMC Med. 2014;12:131.
11) Cronin AJ. Transplants save lives, defending the double veto does not: a reply to Wilkinson. J Med Ethics. 2007;33(4):219-20.
12) España. Organización Nacional de Trasplantes, Ministerio de Sanidad, Consumo y Bienestar Social. Memoria de Actividad ONT 2016 [Internet]. Madrid: ONT, 2016. Disponible en: http://www.ont.es/infesp/Memorias/Memoria%20Donaci%C3%B3n%202016.pdf (citado 15-08-2018).
13) Douglas JF, Cronin AJ. The Human Transplantation (Wales) Act 2013: an Act of Encouragement, not Enforcement. Modern Law Rev. 2015;78(2):324-48.
14) McCartney M. Margaret McCartney: When organ donation isn't a donation. BMJ. 2017;356:j1028.
15) Domínguez-Gil B, Matesanz R. International Figures on Organ Donation and Transplantation Activity. Year 2016 [Internet]. Strasbourg: European Directorate for the Quality of Medicines, HealthCare of the Council of Europe, 2017. 70 p.
16) Quigley M, Wright L, Ravitsky V. Organ donation and priority points in Israel: an ethical analysis. Transplantation. 2012;93(10):970-3.
17) Stoler A, Kessler JB, Ashkenazi T, Roth AE, Lavee J. Incentivizing Authorization for Deceased Organ Donation With Organ Allocation Priority: The First 5 Years. Am J Transplant. 2016;16(9):2639-45.
18) Schmidt VH, Lim CH. Organ transplantation in Singapore: history, problems, and policies. Soc Sci Med. 2004;59(10):2173-82.
19) Krieger Kahan S. Incentivizing Organ Donation: A Proposal to End the Organ Shortage. Hofstra Law Rev. 2009;38(2):757-91.
20) Hughes P. Presumed consent: state organ confiscation or mandated charity. HEC Forum. 2009;21(1):7.
21) Morais M, da Silva RC, Duca WJ, Rol JL, de Felicio HC, Arroyo PC Jr, et al. Families who previously refused organ donation would agree to donate in a new situation: a cross-sectional study. Transplant Proc. 2012;44(8):2268-71.
22) Ralph A, Chapman JR, Gillis J, Craig JC, Butow P, Howard K, et al. Family perspectives on deceased organ donation: thematic synthesis of qualitative studies. Am J Transplant. 2014;14(4):923-35.
23) West R, Burr G. Why families deny consent to organ donation. Aust Crit Care. 2002;15(1):27-32.
24) Ghorbani F, Khoddami-Vishteh HR, Ghobadi O, Shafaghi S, Louyeh AR, Najafizadeh K. Causes of family refusal for organ donation. Transplant Proc. 2011;43(2):405-6.
25) Shaw D, Elger B. Persuading bereaved families to permit organ donation. Intensive Care Med. 2014;40(1):96-8.
26) Neate SL, Marck CH, Skinner M, Dwyer B, McGain F, Weiland TJ, et al. Understanding Australian families' organ donation decisions. Anaesth Intensive Care. 2015;43(1):42-50.
27) De Lora P. What does "presumed consent" might presume? Preservation measures and uncontrolled donation after circulatory determination of death. Med Health Care Philos. 2014;17(3):403-11.
28) Isdale W, Savulescu J. Three proposals to increase Australia's organ supply. Monash Bioeth Rev. 2015;33(2-3):91-101.
29) Argentina. Ley 27.447 de trasplante de órganos, tejidos y células [Internet]. Disponible en: https://www.argentina.gob.ar/sites/default/files/ley-27447.pdf (citado 15-08-2018).
Cómo citar este artículo: Zúñiga-Fajuri A, Molina-Cayuqueo J. Organ donation and family refusal. Bioethical reasons for a change. Rev Nefrol Dial Traspl. 2018; 38(4):280-5.
Revista de Nefrología, Diálisis y Trasplante
ISSN 2346-8548 (electrónico) - ISSN 0326-3428 (impreso)
Gascón 88 (1181) Ciudad Autónoma de Buenos Aires, Argentina
Contacto: ban@renal.org.ar